وحید
DEDUCTIVE CLOSURE, SCEPTICISM AND THE PARADOXES OF CO NFIR MAT IO N1
Hamid Vahid
Abstract
To undermine much of what we ordinarily claim to know, sceptics have often appealed to a principle (known as the principle of closure) according to which knowledge (justification) is closed under known entailment. In this paper after expounding the views of Stein, Klein and others, I shall argue that they all fail to take note of different contexts in which the principle of closure is applied. The relevance of the principle of closure for scepticism is then analyzed in the light of, what I call, the 'infectious' character of epistemic contexts. I shall also highlight the similarities in the behaviour of the concepts of justification and confirmation and appeal to certain solutions to the paradoxes of confirmation to provide a comprehensive account of the different instances of the principle of closure.
Much recent work on scepticism has been concerned with a principle according to which knowledge (justification) is closed under known entailment. That is to say if one knows that p and that p entails q then one knows that q. Suppose, for example, you claim to know that you are reading this paper. You presumably also know that if you are reading this paper then you are not a brain in a vat. But, the sceptic argues, you do not know that you are not a brain in a vat and thus, by modus tollens, you do not know that you are reading this paper. In this way the sceptic is able to undermine much of what we ordinarily claim to know.
The issues surrounding the principle of closure are not, however, so straightforward. Because of the contextual character of the concepts involved, there is a great deal of ambiguity regarding the context where the principle is applied. This contextual ambiguity, as will be shown, gives rise to different instances of the principle each requiring a distinct treatment. The failure to distinguish this variety has led to serious misunderstandings regarding both the nature and function of the principle of closure. Another point that will be stressed concerns the similarities in the behaviour of the
1 I am indebted to Professors William Alston and Susan Haack for comments on an earlier draft of this paper. I have also greatly benefited from from discussion with Dr Gary Legenhausen.
concepts of justification and confirmation.2 Ther are both context dependent and both give rise to similar puzzles. Indeed, as I shall explain, the solution to certain paradoxes of confirmation can be exploited to clarify and sharpen our understanding of the principle of closure. I begin, however, with Dretske's presentation of the problem of deductive closure.
Discussing this question in an early article Dretske posed the problem in terms of penetratability of certain operators.4 Some of these operators such as 'it is true that' and 'it is necessary that' penetrate to every necessary consequence of the propositions upon which they operate; if it is true that p and p entails q then it is true that q. At the other end of the spectrum lies the class of nonpenetrating operators such as 'it is a mistake that' or 'it is accidental that'. They fail to penetrate to some of the most elementary logical consequences of a proposition. It may have been a mistake that Bill and Susan married each other but not a mistake that Bill married. Dretske also identifies a class of semi-penetrating operators which falls between these two extremes. These include epistemic operators such as 'knows that', 'has reason to believe that', etc. One of the examples that Dretske gives is the following. Suppose you take your son to the zoo where you see several striped animals. When asked about the identity of the animals you tell him that they are zebras. You know this because you know what zebras look like and the animals are kept in a cage marked "zebras". Being a zebra, however, implies that the animal is not a disguised mule. According to the principle of closure by knowing these facts you also know that the animals are not disguised mules. Dretske denies that such a consequence follows and, thus, rejects the closure principle. He argues that your adequate evidence for 'That is a zebra' ceases to be adequate for 'That is not a mule with stripes painted on it'. That evidence has been effectively neutralized. It no longer supports the claim that these are not mules disguised to look like zebras. The evidence did not involve checking with the
zoo authorities or examining the animals closely enough.
Dretske also offers an explanation for the failure of the principle of closure. Knowing that this animal is a zebra, he claims, does not necessarily involve knowing that it is not a disguised mule. This is because knowing that x is A always involves knowing it within a framework of relevant alternatives B, C, D. So that by changing the set of contrasts one also changes what a person is said to know. Epistemic operators, thus, penetrate only to those contrast consequences which belong to the set of relevant alternatives. This explains why we can claim to know that this animal is a zebra without knowing that it is not a disguised mule. The possibility of the animal being a disguised mule is not relevant in the (ordinary) context of the example and, thus, need not be ruled out in order for us to know.
I shall now turn to two different sorts of responses to the above claim. Gail Stine has offered another account of this example, on the relevant alternative view, in which one need not give up the principle of closure.5 On the relevant alternative view to say that S knows that p is to presuppose that not-p is a relevant alternative. On Stine's account, however, this is viewed as a pragmatic rather than a semanticf.resupposition thus having the Gricean property of cancellability. It is therefore possible for 'S knows that p' to be true while 'not-p is a relevant alternative' is false. So although it may sound misleading to claim to know that the animal is not a disguised mule but this does not mean that the claim is false. One can cancel, says Stine, the implication that one has investigated the questions raised by the consequence. Stine offers no direct argument in support of her account. She only suggests that we do not need evidence to know a proposition and that we do not even have evidence for the claim that the animal is a zebra. As she does not elaborate on these claims it is very difficult to evaluate her defence of the principle of closure. I thus turn a different style of defence proposed by Peter Klein.7
Klein thinks that the hostility towards the principle of closure is the result of confusing it with a different but false epistemic principle according to which justification is transitive i.e., if the evidence ejustifies p for Sand p entails q, then ejustifies q for S. But,
Klein claims, justification is not transitive and the principle of closure does not depend on that, for the justification of q is already secured via p itself. If e justifies p for S, then p, on its own, would provide adequate justification for anything that is entailed by it. So in the zebra example, ifl am justified in believing that the animal is a zebra, I would, a fortiori, be justified in believing anything entailed by this including the consequence that the animal is not a disguised mule.
As the preceding remarks show there are conflicting intuitions regarding the principle of deductive closure. On the one hand there is Dretske's claim that certain consequences of a proposition raise possibilities that affect the epistemic status of the evidence, thus undermining our claims to know those consequences. On the other hand there is the intuition expressed by Stine and Klein in their claim that entailments are justification (knowledge) preserving - though each has a different style of explaining away the contrary intuition. The whole issue has, however, been obscured by the fact that the parties involved have all failed to take note of different contexts in which the principle of closure may apply. They only consider the application of the principle across contexts i.e., where the initial context is allowed to change as a result of taking new information into account. There is, however, another instance of the principle of closure when it is considered relative to a fixed context where no additional information besides the evidence is admitted. Once the context is so fixed then, relative to this context, the principle of closure may hold. This seems to be what Lehrer has in mind in the following remarks.
The closure principle is intended to concern what one knows at a single time, however, and then it seems correct. The principle says that if one knows that p and that if p then q all at once, then one knows that q as well.8
How are we to account for these conflicting intuitions? Is there a uniform account that could explain them all? Before presenting such an account it will be useful to consider a recent analysis of the principle of closure developed by James White.9 He sides with Dretske on this issue and rejects the principle of closure. His intention, however, is to undermine Klein's defence of the principle of closure. I believe his analysis eventually fails to bring out what is
really at issue but it is instructive to see why it does. To set the stage for discussion however, it should be noted that I shall only be concerned with the application of the principle of closure in justification contexts since this is what is at issue between White and Klein. Any conclusion we reach, of course, also will be true of the application of the principle to those conceptions of knowledge which include a justification clause. So our intended principle of closure states that if the evidence e justifies S in believing that p and that p entails q, then e justifies S in believing that q.
As we just saw, Klein claimed that when the evidence justifies p for S then p is justified simpliciter, thus, providing adequate justification for q when q is entailed by p. White's main contention is that Klein has missed the 'context-relativity' of epistemic concepts. Knowledge claims, he argues, can only make sense against the background of the cognizer's credentials for making those claims in response to the existing questions and doubts. That is to say whether something is evidence for something is not just a matter oflogical relations between believed propositions but is also a function of the questions and concerns existing in that context. He echoes Dretske's claim that changing the context, by adding new information, may neutralize the evidence. So when, in the zebra example, you are asked about the identity of black and white striped animals in a cage marked 'zebra', you are well qualified to answer that they are zebras. But, argues White, when a stranger, having heard a rumour that the zoo is covering up its lack of zebras by using disguised mules, asks you whether the animals are zebras or diguised mules the evidence you had earlier relied on ceases to have any weight. What constitutes evidence for an animal's being a zebra depends on the kind of questions and concerns people have about the animal. By taking a different set of questions and concerns into account we may need different evidence to justify our claims.
To have reason for thinking that the animals are zebras is not thereby to have reasons for thinking that they are not disguised mules, because the latter possibility may raise questions which were not considered when arriving at the belief that the animals were zebras. Given this fact, argues White, the belief that the animals are zebras fails to justify believing they are not disguised mules and Klein's argument is thus proven ineffective. White concludes that the principle of closure is false. He also voices the common wisdom that this neutralizes one important sceptical argument. With the failure of the principle of closure the sceptic is
no longer able to undermine much of what we ordinarily claim to know. Even though we cannot rule out the sceptical possibilities, he says, we can still claim to know much of what we ordinarily regard ourselves as knowing because those possibilities are not relevant to the ordinary situations in which those claims are made.
I agree with much of what White says about the context relativity of epistemic concepts, but he fails, I think, to carry this point to its logical conclusion, and in particular, he fails to provide a comprehensive account of the different instances of the principle of closure. In what follows I shall elaborate on each of these claims beginning with the context-relativity of the concept of epistemic justifica tion.1 0
Justification is a matter of degree. The degree of justification of one's belief is dependent on the position of the cognizer within the epistemic web of evidence and on the amount and strength of that evidence. In short, justification, unlike truth, is perspectival i.e., it is measured relative to subject's evidence. This means that a proposition that is justified for one person can be unjustified for another. Because of the context-dependent character of epistemic justification it is always possible that the cognizer's belief is not adequately grounded so that further evidence may show his initial evidence was misleading.
To see the point consider a case in which, although the subject's evidence in itself provides an adequate basis for his belief that p, that would not have been the case had he been conducting himself properly. It is quite possible that if he had looked into the matter more carefully, he would be in possession of overriders for his evidence for p. In that case we will not want to count the subject's belief as justified, even though the grounds which gave rise to the belief were themselves adequate. Their adequacy is undermined by the larger pcrspcctival context in which they arc considered. 11
Evidence, however, may provide ground for a belief only against the background of one's other beliefs. This means that by changing the background beliefs the evidence may cease to support the belief in question. Not only does the context of the background beliefs
determine the adequacy of the evidence but it also determines which evidence is to be regarded as misleading in the sense of inclining us to form a false belief. That is to say, whether evidence is misleading can only be determined relative to a set of background beliefs. We might come to form a belief as a result of some evidence but the obtaining of a new evidence might oblige us to revise our judgement and make new adjustments. In the light of this new evidence the initial evidence might be judged as misleading. This process may be iterated indefinitely. What this shows is that both the adequacy and epistemic relevance of the evidence is measured relative to the doxastic situation of the cognizer.
Let me illustrate these points by considering an extended version of Dretske's zebra story. ( l) Smith takes his son to the zoo. They come across a cage marked 'zebras' in which there are a number of black and white striped animals. When asked by his son about the identity of the animals he tells him that they are zebras. (2) One of the zoo keepers, Jones, who is a friend of Smith and from whom he has not heard for some time tells him that the manager is using cleverly disguised mules to cover up the zoo's lack of zebras.
- Jones's doctor who is around at that time tells Smith that Jones is currently undergoing treatment for mental disorder which manifests itself in the form of a disposition to spread false rumours.
- An acquaintance of both Smith and Jones informs Smith that the doctor is actually Joncs's nephew who has been trying to deprive him of some inheritance on the ground of mental illness. (5) ...
Let us go through the story step by step to sec how the change in the context of the story affects the epistemic status of the evidence. At stage (1) of the story, the evidence supports, but fails to prove beyond any doubt, the claim that the animals are zebras. So Smith is (defeasibly) justified in believing that they are zebras. At stage
(2) the evidence undermines, but does not conclusively rule out, the claim that the animals are zebras. The evidence of stage ( l) is now regarded to have been misleading. At stage (3) the evidence justifies, but fails to prove beyond any doubt, the claim that the animals are zebras. The evidence of stage (2) is now regarded to have been misleading. At stage (4) the evidence undermines, but does not conclusively rule out, the claim that the animals are zebras. The evidence of stage (3) is now regarded to have been misleading and so on.
This example illustrates that both the adequacy and epistemic
relevance of evidence are measured against the context of the background beliefs of the cognizer. What was justification conferring evidence in one context may cease to be adequate in another context and indeed may be regarded as misleading. This, as we have seen, can only be determined from the perspective of a more comprehensive evidential context. Note that it is irrelevant if the cognizer persists in placing credence in his belief. That does not change the justificatory status of his belief or of the evidence. Suppose at stage (2) of the story Jones falsely (but honestly) tells Smith of the cover up by the zoo's manager and suppose Smith is persuaded that all the appearances are fake but nevertheless persists, on the basis of visual evidence, in believing that the animals are zebras. In such a case he is not permitted to hold this belief because this permission is undermined by his cognitive state at that time. It is sufficient for undermining that a cognizer believes that certain conditions obtain which, if they did obtain, would imply that the target beliefs are no longer justified. 12 I shall now consider the consequences of the preceding remarks for the principle of deductive closure and the problem of scepticism respectively.
It is obvious from our example that what underlies the shift in the epistemic status of the evidence at each stage in the story is the fact that we are assuming that one may be justified in believing something even though one's evidence fails to be conclusive. At no stage in our story did the evidence conclusively establish or rule out that the animals are zebras. In each case the possibility of defeat by further evidence was left open. At each stage the change in the belief context introduced possibilities which affected the epistemic status of the earlier evidence. If this is correct then the failure of the principle of closure in such circumstances is no more than a triviality. For if one and the same proposition can change its epistemic status as the context undergoes change, it would be no wonder if its consequences turned out to have different status in those contexts.
Going back to our story, at stage (1) the evidence based on visual appearances justifies the proposition 'These animals are zebras'. At stage (2) however, the same piece of evidence fails to justify the very same proposition and also its consequence 'These animals are not disguised mules'. In general if evidence e can provide adequate
justification for a proposition in one context but fails to do so for that very proposition in another context, then it may, afortiori, fail to provide justification for the consequences of that proposition. Indeed since p entails p, and p, justified for S in one context, may fail to be justified for him in another context we already have a counter-example to the principle of deductive closure.13 This also explains why Klein's defence is unsuccessful. He claims that when evidence e justifies p and p entails q, we already have a perfectly sufficient reason for q, namely p itself. But if the above remarks are correct and we are considering the principle of closure across contexts then, as we have seen, as the context undergoes change we may no longer be justified in believing p and, consequently, the belief in p would fail to justify the belief in q.
So as long as we are evaluating the principle of closure across contexts (i.e., we allow the context to change) its failure is a trivial consequence of the context-dependence of the concept of epistemic justification. This is not, of course, to claim that any change in the context of the belief will necessarily upset the transmission of justification to its consequences. There may, indeed, be situations where the change in the context is of such a nature as to leave the transmission undistur bed.1 4 This is most evident in cases where pis taken to be its own consequence. Here, as elsewhere, the change in the context need not necessarily involve information which has an undermining character. The subject's justification for p may actually be increased as the result of the added information. But as I am concerned with the possibility of the failure of the principle of closure, the sort of situations that are considered are those that involve cases where the change has an undermining character i.e., it neutralizes the evidence for p and its consequences.
While rightly emphasising the context-dependent character of epistemic concepts, White does not attack the principle of closure exactly in the way I have done and, indeed, our conclusions regarding the significance of its failure for scepticism (as we shall shortly see) are quite different. He also evaluates the principle of closure only across contexts i.e., in a setting where the context is allowed to change as a result of taking new information into
account. Referring to the entailments of p and the possibilities they introduce he says
... bringing up such entailments may introduce a new context with regard to which one may no longer have evidence, a context with regard to which one's reasons are no longer reasons.1 5
But this is not the end of the matter for the principle of closure. Its (possible) failure across contexts does not imply that it also fails relative to a single context, and White ignores this possibility. We have as yet to evaluate the principle in a setting where the context is fixed and no additional information besides the evidence is admitted. Recall Lehrer's remark that the principle of closure 'is intended to concern what one knows at a single time'. Before turning to this problem, however, let us consider the implications of the failure of the principle of closure for the sceptical arguments which exploit it.
The sceptic, we recall, argues that if you know (are justified in believing) that you are, for example, reading this paper then you know (are justified in believing) what it entails, e.g., that you are not a brain in a vat. But since you do not know that you are not a brain in a vat, by modus to/lens, you do not know that you are reading this paper. Now if the principle of closure is false the sceptic's move is automatically blocked. It seems to me, however, that so long as we are allowing the context to change, the failure of the principle of closure cannot stop the sceptic from undermining much of what we ordinarily regard ourselves as knowing. To clarify this point the following remarks are in order.
We saw that our argument against the principle of closure exploited the context-dependent character of the concept of epistemic justification. It was argued that if we are evaluating the principle of closure across contexts, then we need to take into account the possibilities that these contexts introduce; and we saw that the epistemic status of evidence might undergo radical change once these possibilities are taken into account. It is true that by rejecting the principle of closure the sceptic can no longer appeal to modus tollens to deny that, for example, you know you are reading this paper despite the fact that you do not know you are not a brain in a vat. But he can still deny that you are reading this paper via the new context which is introduced as a result of taking the sceptical
possibilities into account. This is possible because epistemic contexts are, as I call them, 'infectious', in the sense that they affect the epistemic status of the propositions involved with them.
Consider, once again, the story of Smith and the zebras. At stage (1) of the story he is justified in believing that the animals are zebras. At stage (2) the initial context changes as a result of the new information (about the fraud) that.Jones adds to it. In the resulting context Jones is not justified in believing that the animals arc not disguised mules but he is equally unjustified in believing that the animals are zebras. So when the context decides the epistemic status of some consequences of p, the verdict may change the status of p itself. When additional information is injected into the context, the epistemic status of all the propositions are affected. A belief once justified in the context may lose its status when new information is added to that context. This also explains why Klein's attack on scepticism is unsuccessful. He thinks that the principle of closure can actually be exploited to defeat scepticism. For if you are justified in believing that you are reading this paper ( p), then, by modus ponens, you are justified in believing that you are not a brain in a vat (q). But if what we have said is correct the infectious character of epistemic contexts undermines the subject's justification in believing p. The mere entertaining of sceptical possibilities is enough to create a setting where the evidence is neutralized both for p and q. As indicated earlier, another context which shares the same property with epistemic contexts is the context of the confirmatin of theories. It is well known that adding new information to the background knowledge affects the degree of confirmation of the theories involved. I shall say more on this point shortly.
Being infectious is not, however, the same thing as being semi penetrating. First of all, 'being infectious' is a predicate of a context, whereas it is an operator which is semi-penetrating. Operators introduce and operate in contexts. They are not identical with the contexts. Secondly, the direction of penetration is always from propositions to their necessary consequences whereas an infectious context may affect propositions in both, and indeed in all, directions. Moreover, it is not the case that all semi-penetrating operators introduce infectious contexts. There are semi-penetrating operators whose contexts are not infectious. It is, I believe, failure to take note of this point that has led philosophers like Dretske to claim that epistemic operators 'share the same logic with such operators as "explains why" '. He exploits this claim to undermine
the principle of closure. Let us consider the example which he gives in support of his claim.
Suppose we want to explain why Brenda did not order any dessert. To do this, Dretske claims, we have to take into account the range of relevant alternatives. He admits that he does not have a theory about what a relevant alternative is, but the case, he hopes, is intuitive enough. When we explain why Brenda did not order any dessert by saying that she was full, we explain why she did not order any dessert as opposed to ordering some dessert and eating it. If we consider a different set of alternatives, for example, Brenda ordering some dessert and throwing it at the waiter, etc., the above explanation fails to be an explanation of why Brenda did not order any dessert even though the fact that Brenda did not order some dessert entails the fact that Brenda did not order some dessert and throw it at the waiter. Dretske concludes that to say we do not know the animals in the zoo are zebras because we do not know that they are not disguised mules is 'as much a mistake as arguing that we have not explained why Brenda did not order any dessert (within the original, normal, setting) because we did not explain why she did not order some dessert and throw it at the waiter'. 1 6
But there is a difference. Introducing the competing possibility of Brenda ordering some dessert and throwing it at the waiter does not invalidate the original explanation of why Brenda did not order some dessert because explanatory contexts are not infectious. When we explain why Brenda did not order some dessert by saying that she was full, our contrast class consists of Brenda ordering some dessert and eating it. This explanation, of course, fails when a new contrast class consisting of Brenda ordering some dessert and throwing it at the waiter, etc., is introduced. But that does not diminish its effectiveness when it is considered against the earlier contrast class. This is because explanatory contexts can be, as it were, partitioned into different sets of alternatives with each partition being completely autonomous. The failure of a certain explanation in one partition does not imply its failure in another partition.
But this is not the case with epistemic contexts. Introducing a novel alternative may neutralize a certain bit of evidence, thus affecting the epistemic status of the proposition whose consequence it is. In the zebra example, the visual evidence justified 'This is a
zebra' but failed to support 'This is not a disguised mule' when the possibility of fraud was raised. The raising of this possibility, however, also affected its ability to justify 'This is a zebra'. In other words, the failure of the evidence to support one possibility infected its ability to support another. This is because in epistemic contexts we are concerned with the cognitive state of the cognizer and cognitive states cannot be divided into autonomous partitions. They are of such a nature that a slight change in their belief repertoire may affect the epistemic status of all the propositions involved. They are, in other words, infectious. Dretske's conclusions regarding the analogy with explanatory contexts are thus, un warranted.
I turn now to the validity of the principle of closure itself. We have already argued that the principle may fail to hold when it is applied across contexts. We saw that in the context in which the possibility of fraud was raised not only the evidence was effectively neutralized for the proposition that the animals are not disguised mules but it also ceased to support the proposition that the animals are zebras. Nothing, however, has so far been said about the principle of closure when it is considered relative to a single context i.e., when no additional information other than the evidence is taken into account, or as Lehrer put it, when the principle is intended to concern what one knows at a single time. So, the question we need to address is whether the principle is correct when the context is fixed. Does, for example, the evidence for 'These animals are zebras' lend any support to 'These animals are not disguised mules' when that evidence is the only piece of information that is admitted? There seems to be an intuition in favour of a positive reply. How are we to account for these conflicting intuitions? To answer these questions we need a comprehensive theory which explains those intuitions. To do this I shall propose an analogy with one of the paradoxes of confirmation known also as the paradox of the ravens. We have already noticed the concepts of justification and confirmation resemble each other to some degree. The analogy can be taken still further by the following observations.
The ravens paradox, in its simple form, has the following structure. Observations of black ravens confirm the proposition 'All ravens are black' while observations of black pens, white swans, etc., are neutral to it. But the proposition 'All non-black things are non-ravens' is equivalent to (and, a.fortiori, entails) 'All ravens are black' and since a white swan confirms the former it
should also confirm the latter which seems paradoxical. To resolve the paradox a number of solutions have been proposed. The difference between these solutions can be traced to the amount of background information that is taken into account. Here I rely on Mackie's account of the paradox.17 I believe a theory along the lines Mackie proposes to account for the conflicting intuitions in the case of the ravens paradox can also be exploited to account for the conflicting intuitions in the case of the principle of closure.
One early solution to the paradox was proposed by H empel.1 8 Consider the proposition (p) 'All sodium salts burn yellow'. Suppose we hold a piece of ice into a colourless flame and it does not turn the flame yellow. This confirms the proposition (q) 'Whatever does not burn yellow contains no sodium salt' and because the two propositions are equivalent it also confirms p which is paradoxical. But, Hempel argues, the paradox is only apparent. For if we take an object whose chemical structure we do not know and hold it into a flame and it fails to burn yellow and subsequent investigation proves that it contains no sodium salt, then this observation would confirm p. The difference between the two cases is only that in the first one we already knew that the substance is ice and ice contains no sodium salt whereas in the second case we did not know this. So, Hempel concludes, the seemingly paradoxical nature of the first case is only due to our allowing the additional information that the object is ice.
So as long as we ignore any additional information we can solve the paradox in the way Hempel suggests. In a setting where no reference is made to additional knowledge we can say the observation of a non-black non-raven confirms 'All non-black things are non-ravens' and its equivalent (and, a fortiori, its consequence) 'All ravens are black'. But, as Mackie points out, given some additional information, for example about the relative size of the classes of ravens and black things, we can solve the paradox in another way. We can still affirm that the observation of white swans confirm 'All ravens are black' but argue that its degree of confirmation is much less than that provided by the observation of black ravens. The admission of more information, as Mackie
shows, might further reduce the degree of confirmation provided by the observation of black pens and white swans.
So if we completely ignore the background knowledge we can follow Hempel and say that the observation of black pens and white swans confirms 'All ravens are black'. But Hempel's solution is unrealistic for it requires the theorist to ignore much of what he knows and regard the evidence ('This thing is non-black and non raven') as all the information that is available. This is very odd for it involves a concept of confirmation which is totally at odds with how this concept is understood in ordinary contexts.
I think we are faced with more or less the same situation in the case of the principle of closure. Here we are concerned to know whether the same piece of evidence (visual appearances) which justifies p (These animals are zebras) equally justifies q (These are not disguised mules) when p entails q. Imitating Mackie's account of the paradox, we may now explain the apparent plausibility of this principle when it is considered relative to a context where no information besides the evidence is admitted and its apparent implausibility when the context is allowed to change (in an undermining wa y).1 9 The principle of closure seems to hold at a single time (or in a fixed context) because no reference is made to the background information.Just as the observation of a non-black non-raven confirmed 'All ravens are black' in a context where the evidence was the only information available, similarly the evidence (based on visual appearances) which justified 'These animals arc zebras' equally confers justification on 'These animals are not disguised mules' in a context where no additional information besides the evidence is taken into account. So as long as the principle of closure is considered relative to a context where no additional information besides the evidence is admitted and we ignore all the possibilities and concerns, then it holds. That is to say the evidence also provides adequate ground for asserting, say, 'These animals are not disguised mules'. But once we take into account additional information and background knowledge, the evidence might cease to provide justification for 'These animals are not disguised mules' just as the consideration of background
knowledge led to a sharp reduction of the degree of confirmation of the observation of black pens, etc., for 'AH ravens are black'. The principle of closure, thus, fails to hold when the context is allowed to change as a result of taking sceptical possibilities into account.
Although the above account seems to do justice to the conflicting intuitions regarding the principle of deductive closure, there is something odd about the context where the principle holds. Just as speaking of confirmation in a context where the background was completely ignored seemed wholly unrealistic, it is equally un realistic to talk of justification in a context where no reference is made to additional information. It is, of course, possible to talk of justification in a context as bare as this where the evidence is all the information available, but this is far removed from the ordinary contexts where there is always some additional information lurking in the background. It would be very odd to require the cognizer to ignore most of what he knows and take some bit of evidence as the only piece of relevant information. One's judgement as to what is relevant is, of course, a matter of his background beliefs, concerns, etc. To limit the range of relevant information only to the piece of evidence is possible but quite unrealistic. In an epistemic situation to judge whether a certain body of evidence provides adequate justification for some proposition, the cognizer cannot pretend that the evidence is the only relevant piece of information available. On the contrary, since he approaches the situation in the light of his
background knowledge, judgements as to what is relevant cannot be limited to the evidence alone. It is only by assuming that the cognizer's mind is completely blank that the evidence can be regarded as the only piece of information.
Indeed mere reflection on the consequences of a justified belief p (together with one's background beliefs) may create a setting where the evidence is neutralized for those consequences and even the justification for p is undermined - this is in fact the case with the application of the principle of closure to the sceptical consequences of our ordinary beliefs. In such contexts the mere entertaining of sceptical thoughts (against the background of one's beliefs) affects the range of relevant information. I conclude, thus, that although the principle of closure may always hold in contexts where the background information is reduced to a bare minimum, this is not what happens in ordinary epistemic situations where the cognizer's beliefs are always formed against the background of some information. Under such circumstances it is always possible that
the consideration of background knowledge involves information that disturbs the transmission ofjustification via entailment.
Institute Jar Studies in Theoretical Physics and Mathematics (IP M)
PO Box 19395-5746
Teheran - Iran.
- ۹۶/۰۸/۰۵